Posts
New Encyclical on Faith
/I just read the new encyclical on faith. Although it is not aimed at a philosophically or theologically sophisticated audience, it has some material that is worth thinking about in the light of St. Thomas and Thomism. For instance, there is some discussion of the “light of faith” and the rationality of religious belief. For more on this issue, a good place to look is Romanus Cessario’s Christian Faith and Theological Life, Chapter 2. For more detailed treatments, Santiago Ramirez’ commentary on the discussion of faith in the Secunda Secundae (De Fide Divina) is one of the best presentations of faith written in the twentieth century. You can get it here: http://www.sanestebaneditorial.com/coleccion.aspx?id=11. Furthermore, in my view Garrigou-Lagrange’s De Revelatione is in some ways more important than Garrigou-Lagrange’s own commentary on faith in the Secundae Secundae.
The evolution of Maritain's later political thought
/I recently reviewed a book on Jacques Maritain’s political theory for The Catholic Historical Review. The book is by Daniele Lorenzini and is entitled Jacques Maritain e i diritti umani: Fra totalitarismo, antisemitismo e decmocrazia (1936–1951). It was published last year by Morcelliana. Since I have posted on Maritain’s political theory (of which I am a critic) in the past on Thomistica (here, here, here, and here) I thought that I would offer some excerpts in the present post from my review.
Here’s the first paragraph:
This is an historical rather than philosophical investigation of Jacques Maritain’s political thought, although it should be of interest to anyone who studies this dimension of Maritain’s work. Lorenzini’s central thesis is that there is a significant development in Maritain’s political thought with respect to human rights between Humanisme intégral (Paris, 1936) and his writings during and after World War II, a development that was probably affected in some manner by the French philosopher’s collaboration with the Committee of Catholics for Human Rights [=CCHR] in the United States and its review, The Voice for Human Rights. The earlier development in Maritain’s political thought between his support of the French monarchist movement Action Française and his shift toward a more liberal position is well known. But the later development, treated by Lorenzini in his book, seems not to have received so much attention.
Here are my comments on the second chapter, which is the heart of the book:
The second and longest chapter charts the development in Maritain’s political theory from Humanisme intégral of 1936 to his publications and speeches on political themes in 1943. Lorenzini notes that in Humanisme intégral, although Maritain does open the door to a politically defined social pluralism, he is not yet prepared to defend a human right to practice a non-Christian religion or to follow a non-Christian way of life.The pluralism supported by Maritain in this text is one based on a politically prudent tolerance. Although Maritain does elaborate a theory of “rights of the human person,”he avoids the language of “human rights” or the “rights of man” during this period.The latter language found its way into Maritain’s work for the first time in 1939, in the draft of “The Conquest of Freedom” (subsequently published in 1940). According to Lorenzini, behind the lexical difference there was, for Maritain, a philosophical and theological difference. Talk of the rights of the human person was linked to the Christian understanding of man as created by God, whereas the language of human rights and the rights of man was linked with the secular political theory of the Enlightenment, especially Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Lorenzini contends that Maritain’s experience with the [CCHR] and of the evil of fascism during the war led him to rethink his approach to rights and finally to work out a reconciliation in his own thought between a Christian political vision and the political legacy of the Enlightenment, a reconciliation made clear by the title of his book Les droits de l’homme et la loi naturelle (New York, 1942).
Lorenzini’s tone and judgments in the book suggest that he is sympathetic with Maritain’s political theory. The book seems important to me for its account of the evolution in Maritain’s later political thought on human rights, which, as far as I am aware, has not been much discussed.
In my view this evolution in Maritain’s later political thought is a decline. The position in Humanisme intégral on toleration vs. rights seems more sensible to me. That is not to say that I endorse Humanisme intégral as a whole.
[This post also appears in more or less the same form at the AMU philosophy department blog.]
David Bentley Hart contra natural law
/There has been a serious debate raging (or just “occurring” — “raging” might be too strong) over a critique of natural law theory authored by David Bentley Hart in the March issue of First Things. Edward Feser’s replies (all conveniently linked to here) in defense of classical (as opposed to “new”) natural law theory are worth reading. Actually, Feser not only defends classical natural law theory, he also points out just how confused Hart’s critique is.
Hart replies to Feser’s first reply here. Feser’s reply to Hart’s reply can be found by clicking on the second link in the above paragraph.
(This post also appears at our AMU philosophy department blog.)
Should Italian be the language of the Roman curia? Yes.
/Since Mark just posted on Italian, I figured I would too, albeit in a different context.
Everybody is talking these days about what to do to reform the Roman curia. George Weigel has offered some suggestions of his own at First Things. One change he would like to make is to replace Italian — the common language of curialists — with English. Here are some excerpts from Weigel’s remarks:
Thus a first, specific suggestion for curial personnel reform: strict term limits, by which men and women of proven ability from all over the world would come to Rome to serve the universal Church for a maximum of ten years before returning to their local churches. Service in the Roman Curia would cease being a way to punch one’s ticket for higher ecclesiastical office; it would be a sacrifice.
Then there is language. It’s sometimes assumed that the majority of curialists will always be Italian, which means that Italian-language competence is essential to effective curial service. But why must the majority of curial workers be Italians? The U.N. draws its personnel from New York, Geneva, Vienna, and other locales from all over the world; English is the working language; why should the Roman Curia be different? Because it’s in Rome?
I included the first paragraph to give the background for the second. Here are some rambling thoughts on Weigel’s proposal…
Yes, it’s precisely because the curia is in Rome that the language should be Italian. It would be rather impractical for non-English, non-Italian speakers who come to work in the curia to have to learn both languages.
But why, you might ask, should they learn both? Why should they learn Italian if their work is to be conducted in English, as per the Weigel reform? Because they are in Rome and the inhabitants of Rome — I know this may come as a shock — speak Italian.
True, many Romans do speak English, but those who do speak it do not always speak it very well (or gladly). Also many of the signs in the Eternal City are not in English (e.g., senso unico), the newspapers are not in English, and, generally (and understandably) life in Rome is not lived in English.
Were the curia to adopt English as its official language (and its staff not trained in Italian), we would have every reason to believe that it would become a linguistic and cultural ghetto. The non-Italian speakers in the curia would assimilate to Italian life only with difficulty, which would likely contribute to a negative experience during their time there. Ten years in Rome with a minimal Italian vocabulary? Sounds dismal.
Furthermore, not knowing the local tongue, the apostolates these curial workers could undertake in the evenings and on the weekends would be quite limited.
There is also the perception of American cultural imperialism. Not all Europeans resent that the culture and language of the U.S. have been for many years slowly eroding native cultures of the Old World but many people do (and perhaps should). Undoubtedly, many people would likewise see (whether rightly or not) the curia’s adoption of English as its official language as just the latest outrage in the McDonaldization of Europe (and the globe). If respect for the curia is already low in Europe, this may lower it further. The McCuria?
So why not have the curial workers learn Italian along with English? I said a moment ago that it would be impractical. Two obvious problems on this front are the extra expense and the extra time spent learning a new language. The extra expense and time could easily be avoided — just keep Italian as the language of the curia.
But even if the curialists did learn Italian too, that would not necessarily erase the probable resentment that would arise over the fact that this body’s official language — this important body located in one of the great centers of Italian culture — is English.
Now, Weigel may say that I’m thinking too narrowly here. The Church’s horizon isn’t Rome, Italy, or Europe, but the world. Thus, he goes on:
[T]he Roman Curia exists to support the bishop of Rome in his mission as universal pastor of the Church and its personnel should reflect that global mission—as should its working language. It will take some time to change this, to be sure. But the first head of a curial department who insists on conducting the department’s business in the world language—English—will be doing the entire Church a big favor by modeling a different, more universalist approach to running the engine room.
First, rhetorically speaking, for an American to declare that English is the “world language” and, on this account, to urge a particular group to learn it, well, that’s just a bad move. Whether or not it’s true that English is the “world language,” Weigel will certainly come off as an arrogant Yankee to a lot of people (— I’m only talking about impressions, obviously not facts).
Second, is Weigel trying to drop a not-so-subtle hint to the Holy Father? I have heard — although I do not know this for a fact — that Jorge Bergoglio speaks very little English. Well, he better start learning if he wants to be able to communicate with the “new curia.”
Third, papal and curial documents are already regularly translated into English — and many other languages — although admittedly the Vatican could do a better job about getting all of the documents into the various languages spoken by Catholics and in a more timely manner.
Of course the Church has a universal mission. But the majority of the globe and the majority of Catholics do not speak English and perhaps never will. The most important communication that the curia has with the rest of the Church and the world are the many official documents the dicasteries publish. But, as I have just mentioned, these are already translated into many languages (but, again, there is inconsistency and a better job could be done with it). Should we now translate them only into English since it is the “world language”?
Do you want to speak to someone in the curia but you don’t speak Italian? Rome is full of interpreters. Would you prefer to speak to the person without an interpreter? If you plan to make this a regular habit, learn Italian.
If there are problems with the curia, the language isn’t one of them. But it could become one of them if English were made the official language, or so it seems to me. If Mr. Weigel wants affirmative action for non-Italians in the curia, fine. No problem there. But the non-Italians can learn Italian just as their predecessors.
Don’t get me wrong. I love English. It’s my mother tongue. But imposing it on the Roman curia as an integral part of a reform effort seems silly, not to mention deleterious. And don’t get me wrong about George Weigel either. He is an intelligent man, a faithful Catholic, and I agree with him on many things — but not this one.
(At the risk of seeming to adopt a double standard, I would say that Latin is not subject to all of the same considerations. It has a privilege of historical provenance that English does not and never will have. It will always, in some fashion, be “the Church’s language” even if it was never in the past nor will be in the future a “world language.”)
Some Simple Mistakes about Formal Cooperation
/There’s a need for something like a Catholic Truth Society booklet on “Common Mistakes about Formal and Material Cooperation” (sounds like a bestseller, no?), but as the best is the enemy of the good, here is a short jotting expressing something of what such a booklet might contain.
Let us accept the provisional definitions:
Someone cooperates formally with what another person aims to do, if he shares in the intention of that other person. He cooperates materially, if what that other person aims to do is outside his own intention (praeter intentionem).
Then we say the following:
1. In the definition, to intend is not the same as to want, desire, or willingly to do. If it were, then formal coopertion could never be coerced, because when we are coerced, we do what we do not want to do. Yet clearly formal cooperation can be coerced. (Compare the difference between (i) the bank robber’s holding the gun up to the bank manager’s head to get him to hand over the cash, and (ii) some racketeers through blackmail getting that same manager to obtain cash for them by embezzlement. Although the proper construal of the first case is disputable, the second case is clearly a matter of coerced formal cooperation.) Again, that someone who is coerced into actually doing something does it purposefully —and therefore can be praised and blamed, depending upon the trade-off he preferred— is the best evidence that in an important sense he intended to do it. (Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics III.1 is invaluable for getting a grasp on these matters.)
2. What someone intends is not subjective but rather objective. Hence, he can be wrong about what he intends. Hence, a person’s self-report about his own intention may be mistaken, if he lacks self-knowledge. Indeed, the road to hell is paved with subjectively good intentions. The doctor who says that he intended in administering the lethal dose only to release the soul of the patient from suffering also intended, actually, the direct killing of an innocent human being. In Miss Anscombe’s example, Mr. Truman said that he intended only to end the war and save lives but, whatever he said, because of what he commanded to be done, he thereby intended the killing of women and children.
3. Intention can be implicit and the effect of someone’s “signing up” to do something, rather than express and always prior to the action done. If you will, one’s intention can be an effect of an action rather than an antecedent cause. (J.L. Austin’s theory of perfomative utterances is based on this fact. ) We see this all the time in small steps which already commit someone to the whole (although one may be reluctant to admit that fact); or, again, in actions which are such that we should have understood them but did not (as for example, “Did I really commit to paying $5000 in earnest money by next Monday?”—said incredulously by a man who signed a contract, to his real estate agent: yes, in signing that contract, he made himself someone intending to do that, by “implicit” intention). Again, we find that acts which are good or bad change our will, correspondingly, because they change our intention, formally: for example, an adulterer in retrospect finds that his initial adultery implicitly changed his will in all kinds of ways that he did not understand then.(*)
4. The distinction between formal and material cooperation does not match up with the distinction between ends and instrumental means. That is, it is not the case that what we intend is always an end (although sometimes, on this view, perhaps also the instrumental means to some end, insofar as the means are somehow distinctive of just that end, or somehow “dedicated” to it). To think this is to apply Baconian and Cartesian categories to a distinction which predates the modern era (modern “error”?) and rather finds its proper home in a broadly Aristotelian or classical framework. What is needed for the distinction is a way of individuating kinds of action and kinds of association, such that we can say that something that someone does belongs, or does not belong, in the same kind. These kinds are established by objective, not subjective, “forms,” that typically have a reality in law, social understandings, and knowledge. For example, someone can be trained in defensive actions undertaken with an instrument such as a sword. The consequent mastery is a skill or craft. It is essential to the craft that one undertakes actions proportionate to the hostile force. That someone undertakes such an action when a robber assails him in a dark alley can be established relative to this objective mastery and training, in relation to which, if it “happens” that he kills the robber in repelling him, then the robber’s death is “outside his intention” (praeter intentionem) of self-defense —which is to say that there is an intelligible type of action which this man is capable of undertaking in view of his training, different in kind from murder. (To apply the distinction between “end” and “instrumental means” is most unhelpful here.)
5. Because the “form” of an action is objective, it can happen that because of the circumstances, and especially the social circumstances, in which I do the action, then I am not free to mean by it—to intend—what I wish. If I have recently opened a business in a mafia-dominated part of town, and a mafia goon comes into my store and asks me simply to give some merchandise to him for free, then, in those circumstances, it is not up to me to interpret or re-interpret the action as “oh, I am merely giving away some free merchandise here to promote my business.” Rather, to give the goon the merchandise, in the circumstances, is to capitulate with extortion (and, effectively, to declare that you will later make the required “protection” payments). Or, again, you may go to a party fully planning to rise above yourself and show mere indifference to an enemy who is going to be there as well, but if he approaches you and holds out his hand to shake, then indifference is no longer an option for you. You are not free to shake his hand or refuse to shake it and then claim that “privately” you remain indifferent—at least, not in the way that you understood and intended this prior to going to the party.
6. Once formal cooperation in wrongdoing is established, then the principle of double effect does not apply. Recall that it is a presupposition of double effect that the action that one is doing be either neutral or good: if formal cooperation is established, then the action contemplated is bad. Or, as the moralists say, formal cooperation in evil is always to be avoided. Indeed, if formal cooperation is established, then attempts to apply double effect are instances of “doing evil so that good may come” (or, which amounts to the same thing, so that greater evil may be avoided).
7. Although today people take the default to be material cooperation, and they understand the burden of proof to fall on the claim of formal cooperation, it seems that historically, as a matter of conscience and in the examination of one’s conscience, the default went the other way, and the liceity of a an action of apparent cooperation in evil had to be established by examining it against the traditional list of nine “modes” of formal cooperation (dating from the 13th c and the commentary of St. Antonius of Florence): Did I command wrongdoing, or counsel it, consent to it, flatter someone doing it, shelter someone doing it, participate directly in it, keep silent about it, not impede it, or hide it?
8. Moreover, it seems an historically established fact that formal cooperation, in even serious and obviously wrong actions, can be widespread and, indeed, nearly universal. At least, this last conclusion is one which I am tempted to draw from the case of Franz Jaegerstaetter, who seems to have been the only German who refused to serve in the military under Hitler. Jaegerstaetter said that in conscience he could not cooperate in an aggressive war against innocent French and Russians. Regarded as a traitor or mad eccentric in his own day, his judgment seems to have been vindicated by history, and he has since been beatified. Now if conscience is objective, then people who are similarly situated should reach similar judgments; which seems to imply that many, at least, of Jaegerstaetter’s countrymen did cooperate formally with evil. If the stakes are high (Jaegerstaetter was of course executed as a traitor, leaving behind a wife and child), the evil seems small (will anyone in an army necessarily fire a bullet?), and there seems to be a plausible explanation of why the wrongdoing is praeter intentionem (“I am joining the Wehrmacht only, and surely it cannot be wrong to join in one’s country’s army, which plays a legitimate role of self-defense and is only accidentally connected with aggression?”) nearly everyone will go along. Jaegerstaetter no more condemned those who did not follow him than did Thomas More. Still, as regards the objective moral judgment (not the judgment of subjective responsibility), it seems that nearly everyone in those times cooperated formally in wrongdoing.
(*) On implicit intention, consider this passage from Noldin, Summa Theologiae Moralis (v.2, section 117):
“[Cooperation may be formal in either of two ways:] either α. explicitly, due to the intention of the cooperator, who expressly has the intention of participating in the other’s sin, or β. implicitly due to the nature of the act performed—namely, when someone performs an act that, by its nature or attending to its circumstances, is ordered exclusively to the bad action, for then ipso facto the contrary intention is retracted and [the agent] has the intention of the bad action. For instance, if a man participates in the divine worship of heretics, he cooperates formally, even though he says that he does not intend this.”
___
The appendix to the pamphlet would contain this suggestion for further reading: “The Servant and the Ladder: Implicitly Formal Cooperation in Evil in Light of Veritatis Splendor,” by Rev. McLean A. Cummings, Ateneo Pontificio Regina Apostolorum, Facultas Theologiae, Theses ad Doctoratum in Philosophia, Romae 2009.
The Unthinkability of Compliance
/Dr. Janet Smith, with whose work every Catholic interested in moral theology and philosophy has good reason to be familiar, has recently arguedthat cooperation with the HHS mandate is either remote or at worst mediate material cooperation with evil rather than formal cooperation. In doing so, she proceeds—as does much analysis—along the lines of St. Alphonsus Ligouri, who defines material cooperation as “that cooperation which concurs only with the bad action of the other, outside the intention of the cooperator.” If we mean by this intention of the end, certainly this is one way of committing formal cooperation with evil, but not the only way—one recollects here the very lucid arguments of Dr. Michael Pakaluk on this point—because the object of the moral act must also be good and if it is not the act is evil. Formulations about intention leave one yet with a great measure of ambiguity, precisely because “intention” is an analogical term (it principally refers to the act of the will with respect to the end, but refers also and secondarily—owing to the prior causal role of the intention of the end—to the intention of the object, and in a third sense even to the intention of any part of the motion toward the end).
But certainly there remains the need for the nature of the object of one’s act to be good, since if the object is evil the act is evil. Thomas Aquinas teaches that for the moral act to be good it must not only have a good end, but a good object (and, for that matter, good circumstances), and if the object is morally evil, then the act is morally evil. So, the insistence that if only the cooperator does not intend the same end as the wrongdoer he is not guilty of formal cooperation with evil, implicitly treats the object of moral action as inessential to action. But, to the contrary, St. Thomas Aquinas unequivocally teaches that the object is essential to the moral act, and that if it is evil the action is evil.
So: if one contracts to provide insurance covering a basket of services, knowing that included among these “services” are grave evils, in what sense is one not contracting for them? Of course, coercion is involved. But while coercion can limit or even remove culpability, it does not change the object of the coerced action as such. I may be told that unless I murder some innocent party, my child will be murdered; but if I proceed to murder that innocent “someone” my culpability may be reduced by the coercion, but the object of the act is still wrongful homicide. The question is not whether employers are being wrongfully coerced by the state, as it is manifest that they are. The question is, may one offer insurance coverage for vice because one is being threatened otherwise with the loss of the ability to offer health insurance legally? After all, one presumes that the Catholic institution or party offering the insurance “doesn’t want to” offer coverage for vicious action, and “doesn’t intend”—as an end—that vicious action. If it were true that formal cooperation existed if and only if one intended the same grave evil as that being pursued by the evildoer with whom one was cooperating, then to lack that intention of the end would necessarily imply that one were not formally cooperating. However, this entirely misses the formality of choice and the essential importance of determining the nature of the object of choice. I may not intend something as an end, but still may choose it as object for the sake of the end. If what is chosen is gravely evil, what ensues is a gravely evil action.
What is being argued today is largely that since the Catholic institution only intends providing genuine health insurance as an end, and the mandatory extension of this insurance to vice is not willed as an end by the Catholic institution, it is free to choose to offer an insurance package that covers vicious activities. I say “choose” because although it is under duress, the Catholic institution/employer is still free not to offer benefits at all. And as a matter of unequivocal fact it is the whole package of “services” that the Catholic institution provides access to by providing insurance coverage not only for health services but for vice. It is not only those services that are genuinely ordered to healthcare, but also those that are ordered to abortifacient contraception, to which the insurance provided by the institution gives access. This is a matter of fact. These will be made available through the employer’s health insurance if and only if the employer’s health insurance covers them; and if the employer offers no health insurance, this means that the employer will not make the access to the vicious pseudo-services available through its insurance policy. So: may the Catholic institution/employer offer insurance coverage for health care together with insurance coverage for vice?
If the government mandated that at Halloween mothers must provide one piece of rat poison or one candy bar with a razor blade inside for every three normal pieces of candy, could the mother reason that she is under coercion, and then provide the candy combined with the poison? Would that be only mediate or remote material cooperation? No, because although (hypothetically) she would not will the eating of the poisoned candy as an end, she would nonetheless—under coercion—have chosen to provide it rather than to cease giving candy altogether.
The form of the choice offered to Catholic institutions essentially presents the option of choosing to cooperate—to offer insurance coverage for vice—as a condition for state permission to offer health care. But it is immoral to provide insurance coverage for vice. Period. It is something that no one should do. This is the nature of grave evil, to be something that no one should do. That one ought not to do it is not determined by the Obama administration, nor by HHS; it is determined by the eternal law. Providing insurance to cover vicious activity is an evil; providing access to gravely vicious activity is gravely evil, and one way that one provides access to such activity is to cover it with insurance. Clearly this should not be done. Any institution that cooperates in providing such insurance coverage is indeed cooperating in providing access to gravely vicious activity.
The HHS case is different from that of driving a bank robber to rob a bank, because merely driving the robber to a bank is not specified by the robbery but only by access to the bank. But providing insurance for grave vice, is to set up the means specifically to pursue grave vice: so much so that the insurance policy contains this in its very letter. That is evil. It is not accidental to the provision of insurance coverage expressly for vice that the insurance coverage provides access to: vice. The choice to provide such coverage—even if the alternative is to provide no coverage for health insurance—is an evil choice.
The similar case would be agreeing to arrange “insurance” that covers the provision of “murder services” as a condition for being permitted to continue arranging insurance covering health care (lest one forget that abortifacients are instruments of wrongful homicide). But one comes to full stop: one may not agree to arrange “insurance” that covers wrongful homicide (coercion or no). Therefore, any basket of “services” that offers this cannot be offered. To say that “the benefits of compliance outweigh the cost” is to treat the good of the human life whose extinction one arranges to have funded by insurance a mere deficient utility compared with the cost of insurance.
Not focusing on the nature of choice, the insistence on material cooperation focuses only on intention of the end. But when the object chosen is gravely wrong, the action is gravely wrong, irrespective the goodness of intention. Nor does coercion change anything but the culpability of the agents. Both the intention of the end, and the choice of the means, must be sound: both the end and the object of the action must be good. But it is not good to provide an insurance policy covering both genuine health needs and vicious activity.
In Smith’s analysis, the example of “bundled” evil is given:
The example of buying groceries from a grocery store owned by an abortionist serves here as well. Some of the money we paid for cheerios might go to pay for advertising the abortion clinic but since we do not intend at all to fund abortions and since the amount of the money that goes to abortion is negligible, our shopping at the store is morally permissible.
However, in comparison to the present case, this illustration of bundling seems—and is—trivial. The example is one of very remote material cooperation. For all the reasons already stated, the case of the HHS mandate is a vastly different case.
Lastly, resistance to the HHS mandate is absolutely morally required, because the HHS mandate presumes unilaterally to direct Church institutions to immoral uses, to force the Church to become gravely complicit in scandal, and wholly to invert the sacred purpose that renders Catholic institutions to be Catholic institutions. This is to say that the HHS mandate, mandates a defacing of the Church, a sacrilegious inversion of the purposes that make juridically Catholic institutions be Catholic. For these reasons alone, it is simply impossible for any good Catholic to cooperate with the mandate at the moment when it becomes fully effective. The HHS mandate is insufficient in reason and law to command any well-formed conscience. Of course, it is wrong for Catholic employers as individuals—and indeed, it is wrong for any individual employer who in conscience understands the grave evil of abortifacient contraception—to cooperate with the mandate. But the truth is that the HHS mandate is war on the Church. Thus to be discussing institutional compliance as a plausible option is, to this author’s mind, imprudent and dangerous. One does not cooperate with those who seek to move one through coercion to provide access to vice and to harm the Church. The calendar of the saints is filled with illustrations of the price—and the glory—that this may exact from the conflicted human creature in via… Moral theologians and philosophers must traverse a wide array of difficult and even exotic questions. But the gravitational center of the Catholic response to the HHS Mandate should consist of one immutable syllable: “no”.
Formal and Material Cooperation: Once More into the Breach
/Perhaps the determining element in the question whether institutional cooperation with the HHS Mandate is formal or material consists in the answer to the question whether an institutional choice to provide a basket of services including a malum, implies an institutional choice of that malum. From the vantage of the individual opposed to contraception the answer can be simple: no, because the individual is simply trying to obtain a licit service and being extorted. But there is no prima facie legal or moral obligation for an institution to provide health insurance. Thus, to choose to provide health insurance with malum, is not only materially to include the malum, but to choose to obtain it and to make it obtainable by others. The malum is like an integer added to a sum: it is included in the object of choice as something one is contracting to provide; it is as formal as the presence of a musical note in a musical composition, which would indeed be a different composition without that note, even though as merely a “part” of the composition that note is “material”. Hence, while “material” in relation to the whole ensemble—as is every “part” qua “part”—it is formal with respect to the choice to provide it. I.e., contracting to provide an evil is not merely material inasmuch as the evil is every bit as essential to the basket of items contracted for as all the other constituents, even though the institution might prefer not to choose it. If one views goodness as from total causes, then the addition of one element that is wrong destroys the action. Of course, one might say that it is evil to comply, but only because it is a more proximate material cooperation that is still material. However (assuming a Catholic institution), the end for the sake of which the institute acts is health care; but it does this by formally choosing something that is not choiceworthy. That the malum is only materially included does not change the datum that it is essentially included (and this is the heart of the difficulty: to be merely material in the object does not keep something from being essential to the object). Now, it could be merely material cooperation if the purchase of the evil “service” were per se ordained to a good. But there is nothing about provision of access to abortifacient contraception that is of itself per se ordered to the provision of health care. Thus, the relation between providing contraceptive “services” and providing health care is per accidens, and so one is doing two things, not one, with two species, not one: one is providing access to vice, and one is providing access to health care. These two acts have different species. Acts are specified by their objects. So, one is faced with buying an evil service. How bad is that? Well, how bad is the service? It is a service to help people contracept, often killing conceived children. It might be argued from the vantage of the institutional intention to provide health care, that the malum of providing access to evil is treated as a means although it isn’t one: i.e., “if we are to provide health care, we can only do it by also consenting to provide access to abortifacient contraception; so we must provide access to the latter in order to do the former.” It is not that the abortifacient contraception or its provision is naturally of itself the means for health care (if it were, the species from the intention of providing health care would be most formal and containing) but rather that only by consenting to the provision of contraceptives may one provide what one wants to provide, so that this consent to provide abortifacient contraception is in this way a chosen condition of pursuing one’s intention. But, to reiterate, here too one sees that there is a per accidens order, with two species: providing health care, and providing access to vice. But the act of choosing to provide access to vice, i.e., contraceptive “services,” is not choiceworthy. Of course, it is true that those who consider the cooperation to be proximate material cooperation concur in this judgment. But it is important to realize that what is only materially present in the object may still be essential and therefore constitute formal cooperation. Granted that what is most formal in the hypothetic cooperative action of the Catholic institution is its effort to provide access to health care, it must still choose something that is not choiceworthy in order to proceed, and ought not to do this. Would it be “even more formal” cooperation did the institution positively seek to provide the malum? Yes. But insofar as the institution chooses a package with a gravely evil constituent, irrespective the intention, it is formally in choice embracing that constituent which is deliberately chosen along with the rest, and that includes its nature and per se effects. Of course, when one considers that formally and juridically Catholic institutions are being commanded to give scandal as a condition for obtaining health care—and that the analogously sacred missio the pursuit of which defines such institutions would thus be sacrilegiously perverted by a unilateral act of the state—it is all the clearer that cooperation is absolutely impossible.
The Dubious Guidance of the New Natural Law Theorists on "Formal Cooperation"
/Christopher Tollefsen argues as follows regarding the issue of formal cooperation:
As Sherif Girgis and Robert P. George have explained, formal cooperation involves acts that assist another in wrongdoing, in which the intention of the one providing assistance is precisely to further the wrongful aims of the primary agent. If I provide you with contraceptives in order to enable you to contracept, then I am formally cooperating with you. Formal cooperation is not guaranteed by inevitability: I might know to a certainty that you will misuse some resource or aid I give you. But unless I provide the aid for the sake of so enabling you, then I do not share in your bad intention.
Where the HHS mandate is concerned, there should be little doubt that formal cooperation is not at issue. If the president of a Catholic college is compelled to offer the coverage and complies, it will not be done for the sake of enabling his employers to contracept, but for the sake of complying with a legally authoritative, even if unjust, policy. Accordingly, the form of cooperation at stake is material, not formal.
Alas, this is an aperçu that wasn’t, because the definition of formal cooperation is incorrect. The definition provided implies that only if the cooperator “intends” to bring about the evil involved is the cooperation formal. But “intent” is being used in a peculiar fashion, to denote only what makes the act desirable to the agent and to positively exclude the integral nature and per se effects of that which is chosen. Note how easy this makes avoiding formal cooperation: one may do anything whatsoever provided that one wishes one weren’t doing it. But the integral nature and per se effects of action are always included in the moral object, contrary to those for whom the object of moral action is merely what makes that action appetible to the agent. This is because we choose actions and not merely the formal aspect under which the action is desirable to us—not merely the ratio of the appetibility of an action—but also the action itself. The one who murders “wishing” he were not, but nonetheless choosing to do so, has a conflicted conscience, but is a murderer. The one who offers to provide mass support for the pursuit of sinful actions, while wishing he were not aiding sinful actions, is still “directly” providing such support: “directness” is not a function merely of how one describes one’s proposal for action, but includes the action itself, its integral nature, and per se effects. So, perhaps the reason why someone performs formal cooperation with evil is not because he wishes the evil to be done, but for some other reason: but it is wrong to do. It is wrong to provide mass access to things that one knows are principally sought after for gravely immoral purpose, and the wrongness is formal because providing such access is in essential part defined by its causal implication in depravity and the agent is choosing this causal implication irrespective what he “wishes”. The case is similar with respect to the performance of action generally. For instance, perhaps someone crushes an infant’s skull to remove it from the birth canal and save the mother, and not because one wishes to hurt the child: but this is wrongful homicide and not a medical act, because the act terminates in the child—in such a way as to hurt and kill the child—and not in the putative patient, the mother. Irrespective that the agent “only wishes to help the mother” what the agent is doing is murdering a child. Roman Catholics who wish serious guidance about these matters should reflect that the George/Gigris account is deriving from a theory that countenances the crushing of infant skulls in craniotomy, and that is deeply implicated in the recent abortion (as witness the Lysaught brief defending the hospital) for which the former St. Joseph’s Catholic Hospital has rightly lost its Catholic status. It is wonderful that gifted men of affairs and lawyers are willing to defend the rights of Catholic believers in the public forum. But inasmuch as some of these persons are wedded to a theory in critical contradiction with important elements of the actual moral tradition of the Church—a tradition centrally related to the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas—the long-term benefit is dubious. This begins to be seen in the misportrayal of the Church’s teaching regarding material and formal cooperation, which the NNLT—wedded to a purely logicist insistence on the content of a proposal for action rather than a realist account such as is found in the teaching of Aquinas—cannot help but get wrong, having gotten wrong the analysis of human action in general. The chickens of the NNLT are beginning to come home to roost: NNLT chicken roosting is an emerging bull market.