Now Is Not the Time

In this post, Matthew Dugandžić, Assistant Professor of Moral Theology at Saint Mary’s Seminary and University, addresses the concerns many have about not being able to receive Communion. 

In view of the COVID-19 health crisis, Governor Larry Hogan of Maryland, where I live, issued a stay-at-home order yesterday. The Archdiocese of Baltimore responded by closing all parish churches, such that no more than ten individuals will be allowed to pray inside a church at any one time. As is happening throughout the United States, masses are no longer taking place publicly, but will be livestreamed so that the faithful can watch them from the safety of their homes. The sacraments – including reconciliation – are to be performed only when an individual is in danger of dying.

Many wonder if this is the correct course of action. It does seem unwise to suspend baptisms – which could easily be performed with a crowd of ten or fewer – but what of the cancellation of public masses? Of particular note, Rusty Reno at First Things, has argued that, even if the COVID-19 pandemic be serious, the bishops ought to keep their churches open for prayer. Open, that is, to more than ten people at once. People can make their own decisions about whether to go to mass or not, but the Church herself should be concerned with “the spiritual health of those entrusted to her care,” rather than “imitate the … worldliness of those who work for public health.”   First, we must “grow in our love for God, for only then will we have the firm foundation on which to endure the sacrifices and responsibilities that come with loving our brothers.” In short, spiritual concerns trump temporal ones.

No Christian would deny that loving God is our first priority, or that spiritual goods are higher than temporal goods. But the way Reno paints the picture, there is some conflict between loving God and loving neighbor. We must love God first, and then we can love our neighbor. Closing churches for the sake of people’s health is an inversion of priorities. But the Gospel tells us that whatever we do for the least of Jesus’s brothers, we do for God himself (Matt. 25:40). This includes providing for the temporal needs of our brethren, which can be an act of charity, and all acts of charity are done to show God love (ST, II-II, q. 27, a. 6). Caring about our neighbor is loving God – there is no conflict. Accordingly, there is a time for everything, as Qoheleth says, a time to show our love for God by going to church, and a time to show our love for God by staying home.

Understanding this boils down to a simple axiom that Aquinas often repeats: affirmative precepts are always binding, but they do not always bind. Take something tangible: We should honor our parents. But does that mean that we should be actively engaged in the act of honoring our parents at each and every moment of our lives? No. That would be impossible. Keeping the fourth commandment means never dishonoring our parents and honoring them when the situation calls for it. (De malo, q. 2, a. 1, ad 11). Even when it comes to something as important as confessing the faith, which we give great honor to the martyrs for doing at the expense of their lives, we are not bound to do this at all times, but only “in certain times and places” (ST, II-II, q. 3, a. 2, co.). Going to church on Sunday is an affirmative precept; it ought only be done at the right time.

Accordingly, although loving God is our top priority, we do so in different ways at different times. Some activities, like contemplation, are directly concerned with our love of God. Others, like eating a sandwich, are less so. Saint Paul does say, after all, that whether “you eat or drink, or whatever you do, do everything for the glory of God” (1 Cor. 10:31). As Aquinas explains, this means that we ought to refer these lesser acts to God habitually (De malo, q. 7, a. 1, ad 9). We eat our lunch as creatures who love God and wish to glorify him, but who also must strengthen ourselves by eating now so that we might glorify him in a better way later. Similarly, a cleric who is normally bound to say matins in the morning might instead say them in the evening if something important – like his duty to teach a class – prevents him from saying matins at the normal hour (Quodlibit q. 14, unic.). We, as temporal creatures, simply cannot be in a state of prayer at all times (ST, II-II, q. 83, a. 14, co.).

This is all to say something simple: life is full of goods – both spiritual and temporal – that we ought to pursue. And these goods are certainly hierarchical, with the good of loving God at the very top of the hierarchy. And yet we are not called to pursue every one of these goods explicitly at every time, but rather at the right time. And some situations call for us to pursue a lower good than the one that we might otherwise pursue. If a person were at Sunday mass and a fire broke out in a building across the street, should the person wait for mass to end before going to help people out of the burning building? Or should he leave mass and help the people in need before it is too late? Clearly, if a person who is merely sick with a contagious illness does not have to attend Sunday mass (and, indeed, ought not, since the person should take care of his health now so as to render due worship to God later, and should be mindful not to spread his disease to people who may be vulnerable to it), then certainly neither does the person who has an opportunity to help those in grave need right now.

And this is not so much different from the situation that we are in. Our neighbors are in grave need. They are in need of us not to go to mass. Many of us could be carrying the novel coronavirus without knowing it. We could easily pass it on to those who may suffer gravely from it. Simply telling everyone to make up their own minds about whether to go to mass would not suffice. Many people who should not go will end up going, some out of ignorance, some out of misplaced guilt at missing Sunday mass, some for other reasons. The most effective way to deal with the preset problem is to make it clear to people that they, in these circumstances, have no obligation to go to mass and indeed ought not. This is not a paternalistic imposition, but rather a service that those who have authority over us are providing for us.

This decision to close churches for public prayer need not be seen as spiritual abandonment. And it is not. The faithful still have means at their disposal to receive the grace of the Eucharist in spiritual Communion. There are dozens upon dozens of options available for Catholics to livestream different liturgical services. The sacraments can still be physically administered in cases of grave need. But more importantly, this is an opportunity to forego a great good for the sake of helping our neighbors, all in view of rendering glory to God. It so happens that in this circumstance, the way we should render God his glory is not by going to mass, but by depriving ourselves of this blessed opportunity for the sake of our brothers in Christ. Being deprived of the opportunity to worship in communion and to receive the Eucharist physically is an opportunity to reflect on just how great these gifts are, which should cause us to long for them even more than we normally do, and to find even more joy in them when we finally get to return to them, thus showing God even greater glory. Worshiping in communion is a great thing. Receiving the Eucharist physically is a great thing. Normally, we ought to do these things. But now is not the time.

1 Comment

Ryan J Brady

Dr. Brady is an associate professor of Theology at St. John Vianney College Seminary and Graduate school. He has taught courses in theology, classics and early Christian studies at St. Vincent de Paul Regional Seminary and Ave Maria University. Subsequent to a few semesters of study at Thomas Aquinas College, he graduated from La Salle University in Philadelphia with a B.A. in Religion. After receiving a Masters degree in Systematic Theology from Christendom Graduate School (where he was the valedictorian) he defended his doctoral dissertation “Aquinas on the Respective Roles of Prudence and Synderesis vis-à-vis the Ends of the Moral Virtues” with distinction and received his Ph.D. in Systematic Theology. His forthcoming book with Emmaus Academic is entitled, “Conforming to Right Reason.”

Antoine Touron’s 'La Vie de S. Thomas d’Aquin'

The attempt to provide an ‘objective’ and accurate description of the life of St. Thomas by contemporary biographers can sometimes lead to losing sight of the central motives of his thought and spirituality. In addition to these biographies, therefore, it is worthwhile to read La vie de S. Thomas d'Aquin de l'Ordre des Frères Prêcheurs, Docteur de l'Église, avec un exposé de sa doctrine et de ses ouvrages, first published in 1737 by Antoine Touron (1686-1775), the French Dominican biographer and historian.

While Books I-III (pp. 1-312) and V-VI (516-696) - which deal with his life, work and reception by the Church - can be easily found in modern biographies, it is Book IV (pp. 322-504), the center piece of the work, which intends to give us an insight into the heart of the saint and scholar. While a mere list of the chapters and subchapters of Book IV (see here) will be enough to inspire readers (and perhaps a translator), here follows just one beautiful observation of Antoine Touron O.P.

Touron devotes a chapter of Book IV to “the sources from which St. Thomas has drawn science and wisdom”. In describing the second source as “the knowledge and love for Jesus Christ and His Cross”  - the first source being “the intimate union with God through continual prayer” – he notes that “the Cross of his Savior was his first Book, the great object of his meditations, the rule of his entire life. It is at the foot of the Cross that he humiliated his mind in order to merit the understanding of the Mysteries. At the foot of the Cross he purified his heart in order to render it able to receive such understanding.” Touron continues by saying that “this divine wisdom, which the Apostle acquired in the third heaven, the beloved disciple on the breast of the Savior, St. Augustine in the Scriptures, St. Thomas learned at the feet of the Cross. The wounds of Jesus Christ were the masters whom he consulted in his doubts, and to whom he listened in his difficulties. […] It is from this source that he drew the principles of his science, the abundance and purity of his doctrine.”

Touron 1740 La_vie_de_saint_Thomas_d_Aquin-6-page-001.jpg
Comment

Jörgen Vijgen

DR. JÖRGEN VIJGEN holds academic appointments in Medieval and Thomistic Philosophy at several institutions in the Netherlands. His dissertation, “The status of Eucharistic accidents ‘sine subiecto’: An Historical Trajectory up to Thomas Aquinas and selected reactions,” was written under the direction of Fr. Walter Senner, O.P. at the Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas (Angelicum) in Rome, Italy and published in 2013 by Akademie Verlag (now De Gruyter) in Berlin, Germany.

New Book on Lying and Homosexual Activity

John Skalko has published a book, Disordered Actions: A Moral Analysis of Lying and Homosexual Activity.

https://www.amazon.com/Disordered-Actions-Analysis-Homosexual-Activity/dp/3868382186/ref=sr_1_1?keywords=disordered+actions&qid=1563825462&s=books&sr=1-1

There is to the best of my knowledge no previous scholarly book-length defense of Aquinas on homosexuality.  Prior to the publication of Skalko’'s work, you only had Gareth Moore and Adriano Oliva, both Dominicans, who either attacked or reinterpreted Aquinas. I reviewed Oliva’s work for The Thomist, and it seemed to me either incompetent or dishonest.

"Apostle to the Apostles"

Titian, Noli me tangere, 16th century

Three years ago, Pope Francis elevated the July 22 liturgical memorial of St. Mary Magdalene to the dignity of a feast day to be celebrated universally throughout the Church on par with feasts of the apostles. He also gifted the great saint with the title of “Apostle to the Apostles,” an ancient designation first tokened in part by St. Thomas Aquinas himself. In his Lectura super Ioannis, we find this passage in caput 20, lectio 3:

“Note the three privileges given to Mary Magdalene. First, she had the privilege of being a prophet because she was worthy enough to see the angels, for a prophet is an intermediary between angels and the people. Second, she had the dignity or rank of an angel insofar as she looked upon Christ, on whom the angels desire to look. Third, she had the office of an apostle; indeed, she was an apostle to the apostles insofar as it was her task to announce our Lord’s resurrection to the disciples. Thus, just as it was a woman who was the first to announce the words of death, so it was a woman who would be the first to announce the words of life.” (2519)

Aquinas affords a triple dignity to Mary Magdalene, the first disciple to bear witness to the resurrected Jesus Christ: she is a prophetess, an angelic messenger, and an apostolic figure. As a witness to the resurrection and as a bearer of the glad tidings from the resurrected Christ, Mary is portrayed by St. John as an apostle commissioned by Jesus himself to the apostles. It should not surprise us that the Common Doctor picks up on this archetypal role filled by the Magdalene.

On this universal feast of the Church, let us give thanks to God for the evangelical witness of St. Mary Magdalene who “first announce[d] the words of life,” and for our indebtedness to St. Thomas Aquinas for naming her “apostle to the apostles.”

With thanks to Rev. John Ubel for the inspiration for this post.

Leonard E. Boyle O.P.

Boyle Leonard E. (1923-1999).jpg

On the 25th of October 2019, the Thomistic community will commemorate the 20th anniversary of the death of father Leonard  E. Boyle O.P. (1923-1999) who taught for many years at the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies (before becoming Prefect of the Vatican Library in 1984) and as such had a formative influence on an entire generation of Thomists. His most important publications on Thomas were collected in Facing History: A Different Thomas Aquinas (Louvain-la-Neuve: FIDEM, 2000). His enduring scientific legacy for the Thomistic community centers in my modest view around two novel contributions. First, the historical situatedness of Thomas’ moral thought, in particular within the Dominican educational context of the 13th century, a topic which he developed from a much wider perspective as well (see his collection Pastoral Care, Clerical Education and Canon Law, 1200-1400, London: Variorum Reprints, 1981 and in particular his “Notes on the Education of the Fratres Communes in the Dominican Order in the Thirteenth Century”). Understanding the mindset of Thomas’s most influential contribution, the Summa theologiae and in particular the novelty of the Secunda pars requires taking into account father Boyle’s work and its continuation by J.-P. Torrell, M. Michele Mulcahey and others. His second contribution concerns the notorious alia lectura fratris Thome, that is to say, a set of marginal annotations in the Oxford manuscript Lincoln College lat. 95. In his 1980 article, which reads like a thrilling detective’s quest, father Boyle turns father Hyacinth Dondaine’s arguments around and concludes in favor of the authenticity of these marginal notes. The notes in their entirety were finally published by John P. Boyle as Lectura romana in primam Sententiarum Petri Lombardi (Toronto: PIMS, 2006). The debate that followed this edition, both regarding the authenticity of the content of the notes as well as the attribution of the different hands, remains ongoing but in any case testifies to the ingenuity of father Boyle and the importance of returning to the manuscripts. (A brief survey of the discussion can be found in Torrell’s new edition of his Initation à saint Thomas d’Aquin. Sa personne et son oeuvre (Paris: Cerf, 2015, 73-77).

Father Boyle, who both as an Irish Dominican and an as historian of the Order’s achievements, took a particular interest in the church of San Clemente in Rome. This 12th century church, which has been in the care of the Irish Dominicans since 1667, is in reality a three-tiered complex of buildings. The present church is built upon a 4th century basilica which in turn is built upon a pagan temple for the worship of Mithras. During the recent Symposium Thomisticum IV, held in Rome, we were given a tour of the complex and it is there where I was able, at the level of the 4th century basilica, to take this picture of the tomb of father Boyle. R.I.P.

Boyle Tomb San Clemente.jpg
Comment

Jörgen Vijgen

DR. JÖRGEN VIJGEN holds academic appointments in Medieval and Thomistic Philosophy at several institutions in the Netherlands. His dissertation, “The status of Eucharistic accidents ‘sine subiecto’: An Historical Trajectory up to Thomas Aquinas and selected reactions,” was written under the direction of Fr. Walter Senner, O.P. at the Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas (Angelicum) in Rome, Italy and published in 2013 by Akademie Verlag (now De Gruyter) in Berlin, Germany.

On Reading Thomas

Thomas is always a joy to read. An ordering of the mind. A judicious approach, multifaceted and subtle yet not tangled and unruly.

Now and again, one tastes a bit of the angelic. Things in the world recede in their tumbling chaos. Not, mind you, to the loss of their detail. But their real being, their weight, and their true finality appears through the din of what would otherwise, deafening me, make lame my mind’s eye so that I could not feel all their stuff. Now and again, one of Thomas’s insights gathers one on high to taste this angelic stance, at once very human.

So it was, this morning, in reading his ‘On Judgment.’ Who would have thought, before turning these pages, that judgment is an act of justice? Not I. Often, Thomas is intuitive. Not this time. At any rate, he goes on to cite Aristotle: People seek refuge in a judge, as in a sort of living justice. (And so, this time, the insight is Aristotle’s. But who owns an idea anyway? We are all in the school. It is habits of mind, not ownership; truth, not persons, for which we are most eager.)

Reading this peculiar passage brought a recollection of things past: children’s voices raised in animosity. A dispute. An argument. Recourse! Recourse to whom? To a third party. To Mom or Dad. All those times that seemed so wearisome, so bothersome, …. All these now gathered together in the insight: people seek refuge in a judge. Why? They want a right saying. How consoling to read the Master and to have meaning found where one saw only chaos.

Merry Christmas!

The introit for yesterday’s vetus ordo Mass (Dominica infra Octavam Nativitatis) is quite beautiful:

Dum medium silentium tenerent omnia, et nox in suo cursu medium iter haberet, omnipotens sermo tuus, Domine, de caelis a regalibus sedibus venit. Dominus regnavit, decorum indutus est: indutus est Dominius fortitudinem, et praecinxit se.

The words are taken from Wisdom 18:14-15 and Psalm 92:1.

A comedy in four acts (updated)

After Jean-Luc Marion’s critique of Aquinas as an ontotheologian in L’idole et la distance (1977) and Dieu sans l'être (1982) people made a big deal of an alleged retraction in “Saint Thomas d’Aquin et l'onto-théo-logie” (1995) published in Revue thomiste. The text was even inserted into the 2013 edition of Dieu sans l'être as a supplement. In Marion’s “defense” of Aquinas against the charge of ontotheology in the Revue thomiste article he tells us that we should seriously consider the possibility that the esse that Aquinas predicates of God has no positive content but is purely a nom négatif. Indeed,

pourquoi pretendre le traiter comme un nom affirmatif, fournissant l’équivalent d’une essence, l’équivalent d’une concept, l’équivalent d’une définition, l’équivalent d’une connaissance?

Is this Marion channeling Sertillanges? Is he in earnest or is it all in jest?

I think it was the latter. Marion published an article in a 2004 issue of Conférence in which he argued once again, as he had before 1995, that Aquinas limits God’s transcendence by predicating esse of him.

Marion’s argument in the 2004 piece is weak, to say the least. He begins, harmlessly enough, by explaining that, for Aquinas, God’s esse and essentia aren’t really distinct from each other, as they are in creatures, but identical. This means that God isn’t simply an ens. However, he goes on, this won’t do to ensure God’s transcendence.

Que la transcendance de Dieu ne joue plus à l'intérieur d'un concept d'étant […] ne suffit pas à la libérer; puisqu'elle ne s'ouvre encore que dans l'interstice entre l'essence et l’esse, donc definitivement dans l'horizon de l’être.

It’s unclear whether être here is meant to refer to Heideggerian Sein (which Marion had mentioned in the previous paragraph). If it is, then Sein, being finite (as it surely seems to be), would necessarily limit God’s transcendence were he subject to it. But why should we think that esse and essentia as Aquinas predicates them of God can be reduced to Sein? If this is what Marion has in mind, he doesn’t explain why we should buy it. On the other hand, if être isn't Sein but has a more indefinite reference, why should we think it limits God? Marion doesn’t explain. Of course, we know that Aquinas holds that divine esse is unlimited (cf., e.g., ST, Ia, q. 13, a. 11). If God is without limits, then he can’t help but be transcendent. How does Marion show that Aquinas is wrong to think that divine esse is unlimited? He doesn’t.

The title of the 2004 article is “L’impossible pour l’homme – Dieu.” Marion presented an English version of it at one of John Caputo’s “Religion and Postmodernism” conferences at Villanova. But I don’t remember whether that was before or after the French version appeared.

Several years ago I thought about publishing something about all of this but I never got around to it. Maybe it doesn’t require any drawn-out discussion. The basics can be noted without much ado. In any event, let this blog post suffice for now.

(This is a reblog of a post of mine at the AMU Philosophy Department blog.)

***

Post scriptum (12.7.18): I should make it clear that I do think that, for Aquinas, esse as predicated of God does have some positive content. It’s not merely a negative name, as Marion suggests in the Revue Thomiste article. In the general debate about Aquinas’s apophaticism, I side with Maritain (and Garrigou, Cajetan, and — with some qualifications — Milbank) against Sertillanges.

Thomas Aquinas and Canon Law. T.A.C.L.

Justin M. Anderson (Seton Hall University), Mark Johnson (Marquette University), Atria Larson (St. Louis University) and myself are at the initial stages of setting up a “Thomas Aquinas and Canon Law. International Working Group” [T.A.C.L.]. The aim of T.A.C.L. is to bring together scholars of Thomas and of (medieval) canon law in order to trace and study the connections between these two fields.

In particular, medieval ecclesiastical law as a fount of Thomas’ own thought remains an important source which thus far has seem to be neglected.  Yet, that body of law holds significant importance in Aquinas’s moral, sacramental thought, etc. Below one can read a first description of our project as it can also be found on our website https://thomasaquinasandcanonlaw.wordpress.com/

Scholars who are interested in exploring these connections or can provide us with suggestions and comments on how to move forward are invited to contact us!

“Thomas Aquinas and Canon Law. International Working Group” [T.A.C.L.].

For nearly a century now, scholars involved in the study of Thomas Aquinas’s writings have sought to unearth the historical dimensions of his thought. This has included both studying the development of his arguments, but also his sources. As the decades have progressed, we have learned much of his indebtedness to his own contemporaries, but also to Scripture, to Augustine, to the neo-Platonic authors, and most recently to his Jewish and Muslim sources. However, one historical source that is largely, if not all together omitted, is Aquinas’s understanding and employment of the medieval canon law tradition, in particular both that of Gratian and the papal decretals.

Recent findings, especially regarding his use of the decretal tradition on vows, scandal, and truth have revealed that in all likelihood, Aquinas – like others around him – was both aware of and sought to include the logic of certain papal decrees within his own writings. When Pope Gregory IX wished to compile all the previous compilations into a single work, he asked none other than Raymond of Peñafort, Thomas Aquinas’s Dominican confrère who would – it is said – one day encourage Aquinas to write the Summa Contra Gentiles. Peñafort’s work was published in 1234 and is known as the Liber Extra. While the 12th Century’s Decretum Gratiani easily serves as an early benchmark in the medieval canon law tradition, the Liber Extra likewise serves as a similar point of reference established just under twenty years before Aquinas would begin to write. Moreover, according to the explorations of authors like Leonard Boyle and Joseph Goering, one cannot ignore that both canon lawyers and theologians, especially those in the Dominican houses of the 13th Century, were deliberately concerned with bringing their thought to bear in a practical way in the form of medieval penitentials. Here again Peñafort looms large. The medieval manuals for confessors became a meeting place and, consequently, a conduit of mutual influence between theology and canon law. Of course, the penitentials need not be the only locus of mutual influence. The Leonine edition of Aquinas’s Super Decretalem notes Henry of Segusio (a.k.a. Hostiensis), the author of multiple commentaries on medieval canon law itself, as one of Thomas’s potential sources.[1]

All of this points to a rich new field yet to be discovered. Still, in this nascent field questions abound. What or who were Aquinas’s influences regarding medieval canon law? With regard to what discussions, philosophical or theological, can we find Aquinas employing the decretal tradition? What, if any, secondary literature already exists in this regard? While our project is, at this stage, primarily focused on the influence the medieval decretal tradition had on Aquinas’s thought and writings, not to be ignored are the writings of other 13th Century philosopher-theologians who may also demonstrate the use of medieval canon law in their own thought, or by their writings have influenced Aquinas as a conduit. Furthermore, the causal direction may interestingly be turned around: what influence may Aquinas’s writings have had on later medieval canon law, decretists and/or decretalists?[2] Certainly the role of John of Fribourg could prove instrumental here as well.

Both Thomas’s œuvre and the medieval canon law tradition represent massive sources of knowledge in their own right. Tracing connections will likely require a familiarity with both. While the demand of such a study can make the task appear overwhelming, it is precisely because both fields of learning are so important that the work will prove both fruitful and intriguing.

[1] Sancti Thomae de Aquino, Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M., Tome 40, Pars D-E (Romae, 1968): E, p. 6.

[2] Historians of canon law often make a distinction between “decretists”, who commented on Decretum Gratiani, and “decretalists”, who commented on papal decretals including the Liber Extra.

1 Comment

Jörgen Vijgen

DR. JÖRGEN VIJGEN holds academic appointments in Medieval and Thomistic Philosophy at several institutions in the Netherlands. His dissertation, “The status of Eucharistic accidents ‘sine subiecto’: An Historical Trajectory up to Thomas Aquinas and selected reactions,” was written under the direction of Fr. Walter Senner, O.P. at the Pontifical University of St. Thomas Aquinas (Angelicum) in Rome, Italy and published in 2013 by Akademie Verlag (now De Gruyter) in Berlin, Germany.